Curvature Against the Grain
Present address: Brain and Cognition, Tiensestraat 102 3711, 3000 Leuven, Belgium, Email: koenderinkjan@gmail.com
- DOI
- 10.2991/gaf.k.200124.004How to use a DOI?
- Keywords
- Curvature; Casorati curvature; curvedness
- Abstract
In mathematics “curvature” is described in various ways, but perhaps the most common is as a rate of spatial attitude. Such a definition is similar to the deviation from flatness, where flatness might again be understood (in various ways) in terms of congruence. In classical physics the notion of curvature occurs in kinematics and in the theory of elastic continuous media. The latter aspect is perhaps closest to what might be the notion of “curvature as a gut feeling.” It is least likely that hands-on experience with elastic materials in visuomotor interaction was at the root of the curvature as a proto-concept. One guesses it developed roughly in parallel with the development of spoken language, although “curvature” no doubt was present as a quality of experience with the Neanderthal, say. I consider relations between the very diverse notions of “curvature.” Curvature as a gut feeling survives even today in artistic intuition, it applies to most of us who appreciate sculpture.
- Copyright
- © 2020 The Authors. Published by Atlantis Press SARL
- Open Access
- This is an open access article distributed under the CC BY-NC 4.0 license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/).
1. INTRODUCTION
Is there such a thing as a “History of Curvature?” There certainly are accounts of its history in mathematics [1,2], starting with the geometry of the Ancient Greeks (Euclid of Alexandria’s Elements, ca. 300
In this paper I’ll take a view that goes against the grain. It doesn’t really fit into the huge and beautiful realm I sketched above.
My main point is that the intuitive notion of “curvature” must have been around much earlier. It should not require formal geometry at all. Such gut level notions necessarily derive from experiences involving perceptions and actions in the real world, not the world of Platonic objects.
But although an earthworm will likely have such experiences,3 it never crosses the border between sentience and sapience. Humans do. It is because humans construct things, both formally, but perhaps even more importantly, with their hands. Thinking with the hands precedes thinking in concepts.4
Meaning and understanding derive from what you construct (
2. CURVATURE AT THE GUT LEVEL
You understand curvature when you have constructed it (Figure 1). Biologically speaking, technology is knowledge.
Reflecting on this in such a way, it occurred to me that the understanding of curvature may have commenced from the invention of the bow and arrow. That takes us back in time much further than the Ancient Greeks, all the way to the transition between the Upper Paleolithic and the Mesolithic [9].
The earliest artifacts date from 17,500 to 18,000 years ago.6 From microliths found in the south of Africa one guesses that the origin may go back as far as 71,000 years. After the close of the latest glacial period the use of the bow spread throughout the inhabited world.7
A bow8 essentially consists of the rigid connection of a pair of cantilever elastic beams (Figure 1) attached to a rigid grip. Sometimes it will be of a single piece (of Yew wood, like the English longbow, say), other times it may be a sophisticated composite involving a complex combination of materials, chosen for their diverse physical properties.
From basic elasticity theory [10] we find that the bending moment M of a cantilever beam is proportional to its curvature κ (“curvature” in the modern sense), one has M = κ EI, where E is a material constant9 and I a geometrical constant.10
There is thus an immediate relation between the visible curvature and the muscular effort involved in loading the beam with elastic potential energy.11 The constants are experienced as the property of the bow as a tool, its “feel.”12
The actual physics of the bow is quite complicated [11]. However, the immediate relation between the visible curvature and the muscular effort is what counts here. It renders “curvature” a gut feeling. The construction of the bow turns this gut feeling into a cognitive meaning.
By way of an aside, it might be suggested that the parabolic orbit of the arrow (or a thrown stone, say) might have evoked a feeling for curvature. However, historical evidence pleads against that. Even in the sixteenth century the impetus theory [12], framed by John Philoponus (ca. 530
3. PICTORIAL DEPTH AND THE DUAL NUMBER PLANE
In Figure 3, left the longbow men illustrate the geometry in the plane of the bow. In Figure 3, right we see the personification of Death, standing in a coffin, aim his arrow straight at you. As a spectator, your viewpoint is located in the plane of the bow.
This suggests that – geometrically speaking – we might describe the configuration in planar geometry. In the illustration of the longbow men this is the Euclidean plane. In Hermann Tom Ring’s painting the plane has degenerated into a vertical line.
In order to get to see the plane of the bow, you might be inclined to take a side view of the painting. But this does not work! As you step aside Death is still aiming at you [13]. Indeed, Death aims at all spectators in the space before the painting.13
I know from experience that it is an eerie feeling to be Death’s target when standing anywhere in front of this remarkable work. It must have made a deep impression on people at the time (mid 16th century). Death never misses!
Apparently, the plane of the bow wielded by death is not our trusty Euclidean plane. The reason is that the physical cause of death is a simultaneous order of pigments distributed on a wooden panel by the painter. The figure of death that you are visually aware of only exists in the mind.
The lost dimension is known as “depth” and it is ontologically distinct from the dimensions that span the picture plane [14–17]. The reason is that all points on a ray through the viewing point14 are projected on the same retinal location.
The physics needed here is Euclid’s (Euclid of Alexandria, ca. 300
The relevant geometry is the plane spanned by one dimension that has a parabolic metric and one that has an isotropic metric, often known as the “dual number plane.” [19–24].
The dual numbers15 are complex numbers of the form x + εy, where the complex unit is defined by ε2 = 0 ∧ ε ≠ 0. Notice that
Intuitively, ε is so small you cannot even see at which side of zero it lies. That makes this geometry the natural model of vision. Euclid might have been the first to join the band wagon as he understood the ontological cleft between the dimensions.
Perhaps surprisingly, the whole depth dimension (an infinite line) is squashed into the infinitesimally thin layer of the picture plane! The mind does not need string–theory to sneak in an additional dimension (depth).
Consider the bow of the Death in the dual plane. It would be 1/2εκu2, where the centre of the grip of the bow was placed at the origin. The constant κ would be the “curvature” of the bow, the coordinate u the vertical dimension and the depth the “dual part” 1/2κu2.
In this geometry one defines the (signed) distance between z1 = x1 + εy1 and z2 = x2 + εy2 as ||z1 − z2||= x1 − x2 and – in case x1 ≡ x2 – the “special distance” (also signed) y1 − y2. One also defines the angular metric through the slope of 1 + εy as y [thus 1 + εy is the dual plane version of a protractor (Figure 4)].
Using the conventional definition, the bow is a “circle” in the dual plane, for the slope of the tangent line varies proportional to the arc length (Figure 5). The coefficient of proportionality is the “curvature” κ.
The curve 1/2εκu2 is an example of a circle as a curve of constant curvature (Figure 6).16
The circle of the bow has essentially all of the familiar properties of the Euclidean circle. We compute its curvature as the dual part of
I introduced the dual plane because the calculation of the curvature of a curve f(s) as
Curvature is simply the dual part of the second order derivative of a curve (Figs. 5 and 6). This is because the whole depth domain is shrunk to infinitesimal thickness, like in the painting. Thus |f′|<<1 and consequently the awkward Euclidean expression simplifies to κ(s) ≈ f″.
“Pictorial space” (the world we “see in”, that is in the mind) is far simpler than “physical space” (the world we move in, to naive people the “real” world).
Notice that we have defined “curvature” as a second order derivative here, that is to say, in “infinitesimal” [25,26] terms.18 This is not something that would naturally occur to a Cro Magnon hunter, one of my forebears from the Upper Paleolithic, the Last Glacial Maximum, ca. 48,000–15,000 years ago.
Can we get rid of the derivatives? Well, yes, for most practical purposes we could use small quantities instead of the infinitesimals. But let’s break loose of this altogether.
A straight curve collapses to a point when you put your eye on it. That is one way to check for straightness. This was no doubt the way a Cro Magnon hunter would check his arrows. It is important, for curved arrows do not kill rabbits.
Another way is to notice that something straight can be moved in itself, or that it can be applied in many ways to a copy of itself.
One might also understand curvature as the deviation from straightness. The string of a strung bow looks “straight,” that is why it looks “different” from the bow itself, which looks “curved.”
So we may “know” straightness at the gut level. Then things that won’t fit a straight template might be denoted “curved.”
4. HOW TO MEASURE DEVIATION FROM STRAIGHTNESS
In modern terms we would probably quantify the difference in terms of the root mean square deviations. After a simple shift and picking convenient coordinates, we would measure the difference between the shape {x, y(x)} and the template {x, 0}. The variance would be the average of the quadratic deviation y(x)2 minus the square of the average of the deviation y(x).
But over what stretch should we compute it? We might leave that choice open for the moment and use a weighting function w(x) that depends upon a scale parameter t (say).
Many weighting functions are equally useful, but there are good reasons (because Δw = wt, thus w is the kernel of the diffusion equation [27]) to prefer
We define the mean of a function f(x) as
For f(x) = 1/2κx2 we find that
A different method is to apply the more complicated weight
Using the diffusion equation we have blown up the infinitesimal domain [26] to the trusty domain of spatial intuition [27].
In either case we have got rid of the pesky infinitesimals. We do not require differentiations. We use only averaging over finite regions (weighted integration). The Cro magnon hunter might do the integration by eye measure – no need to understand the formulas.
Of course, the first estimate also picks up other orders (the second does better). One may consider contributions due to other orders, say anxn/n!. For n = 0, 1 they can be nullified by fitting, but orders n > 2 will contribute, although relatively less for small t (their contribution goes by tn/2) (see [28]).
The standard definition does not have such problems, because it implicitly assumes t = 0 – in itself nonsense from an empirical point of view. Our second method is the remedy for that, it replaces differentiation with integration. The single point (whatever might be meant by that [26]) becomes a blurry finite region.
5. STEPPING A DIMENSION UP, THE DEVIATIONS FROM PLANARITY
Of course, one usually deals with surfaces (as boundaries of volumes) in space, rather than curves in the plane. This is problematic, because our visual field of view is only a topological disk, not a volume. As things in the scene in front of you rotate about general axes this might well lead to surprises.
For instance, in Figure 8, we show an object that may appear (in silhouette) as a triangle, a square, or a circle. Yet it is hardly remarkable, it might well be used as a piece in a board game, for instance.
It might be thought that the outline is not informative at all. That is not quite true [29], but close enough. We’re in an awkward situation (optically, that is), when rotations about arbitrary axes are allowed.
The essence of the problem is that so much remains hidden, that is the sad fact that objects have fronts (visible) and backs (not visible, or “optically specified” as people say). The rotations may change the visibility relations.
Here it helps a lot to move to pictorial space. It has three dimensions, two belonging to the picture plane, or the visual field (your choice), whereas the third is generally known as “depth.”
The former two coordinates span a Euclidean plane, whereas the third is to be considered isotropic (remember ε). Now we can do exactly the same things as before.
The surfaces we consider are parameterized as {x, y, εz(x, y)}. We assume z(x, y) to be smooth and of finite slope, thus
In pictorial space the metric is ds2 = dx2 + dy2, except for “parallel” points that have zero distance, but different depth. Congruences of the first kind are simply the rotations and translations in the picture plane. In order to avoid unnecessarily complicated expressions we will ignore them.
We only consider congruences of the second kind [32]:
In Figure 9, one has some examples. Of course, there are also mixed transformations, but we ignore them. This is perhaps the simplest setting to consider the curvatures of surfaces.
Of the parameters δ, ρx, ρy and σ, δ is a depth shift. We ignore it because observers have no notion of absolute depth, there is no such a thing.
The pair of parameters {ρx, ρy} is very relevant. These are the rotations in pictorial space. To the Euclidean eye they look like shears.
The parameter σ really parameterizes a similarity, that is a depth scaling. It is usually non-negative, although depth inversions are known to occur. In this paper we simply assume σ = 1, but in practice it may vary all over the place.
Such congruences and similarities are freely executed as “mental movements” by human observers looking “into” a picture [32].
This can be understood formally from an analysis of the ambiguity left by the optical structure that impinges on the eye [34]. This has also been a topic of research in computer vision [35].
Notice that the rotations of pictorial space do not permit an object to perform a full pirouette. In fact, they cannot change the visibility relations at all. What is seen at one moment is seen at the next, nothing new is ever revealed.
In a portrait painted en face you will never see the back of the head. It is another reason to feel happy in pictorial space, especially if you are a geometrician.
6. THE CURVATURE OF RELIEF
Now we are ready to say what we mean by (local) pictorial shape: It is the invariant of the congruences defined above. It is easy enough to show that this boils down to a slight generalization of the notion of curvature discussed earlier.
We define the Hessian as the curvature:
Because zxy = zyx, the Hessian is symmetric. As a symmetric matrix it has two real eigenvalues. A congruence of the first kind allows us to change to coordinates such that the Hessian is diagonal. In the two eigen directions we then have exactly the same situation as before in the case of the bow.
Thus there are two novelties. We have a special coordinate system (given by the eigenvectors) and two curvatures instead of one. Since the curvatures are signed (concave or convex with respect to the viewing direction), we obtain three qualitatively distinct cases: convex–convex, concave–concave and convex–concave.
That means roughly, “like the outside of egg shells,” “like the inside of egg shells” and “like a horse’s saddle.” Of course, there are also degenerate cases, such as flat (“like a calm water surface”), flat–convex (“like the surface of columns”) and flat–concave (“like the inside of reeds”).
In the famous catalogue of all conceivable surface shapes, Leon Battista [36] lists all of these (I used his descriptions) except the saddle shapes. This is perhaps remarkable, because Alberti transported himself on a horse, whereas I use a car.19
Alberti’s first division is divided into three:
Restaci a parlare dell’ altra qualità delle superficie, la quale è (per quasi) come una pelle distesa sopra tutta la faccia della superficie. E questa si divide in tre. Imperocchè alcune sono piane ed uniforme, altre sono sferiche e gonfiate, altre sono incavate e concave. a la superficie composta è quella, che ha una parte di se stessa piana, e l’altra o concava, o tonda, come sono le superficie di dentro delle canne, o le superficie di fuori delle colonne,...
One would perhaps expect the saddles here, but Alberti considers the cylinders (both ruts and ridges) instead. There is no mention of anything like a saddle shape.
Gauss famously related the curvatures mentioned here (called “extrinsic” nowadays) to the metrical relations intrinsic to the surface. That is not a topic of this paper, but it implies that you have to crack a piece of egg shell in order to spread it out flat on the table – it simply “has not enough surface area” for that. Likewise, saddle surface have “too much surface area,” so you need to pleat them in order to force them flat.
What is important here is that Gauss defined two surface measures that each somehow summarizes the two curvatures in the eigen directions κ1,2 (say). These are the “Gaussian curvature” κ1κ1 and the “mean curvature” κ1 + κ1. The thing I showed before (Figure 8) has zero Gaussian curvature overall and a non-zero mean curvature only on its conical parts – except for the singular curves and points, that is. The two curvatures are simply the determinant and half the trace of the Hessian.
7. FELICE CASORATI’S DOUBTS
The surface {x, y, x2/2} has mean curvature equal to one and Gaussian curvature equal to zero, surface {x, y, (x2 + y2)/2} has mean curvature equal to two and Gaussian curvature equal to one, whereas the surface {x, y, xy} has mean curvature equal to zero and Gaussian curvature equal to minus one. Both mean and Gaussian curvature may turn out to be zero for surfaces that are evidently non-planar.
This evidently disagreed with Felice Casorati (1835–1890) who apparently entertained the gut feeling that curvature should at least be a difference with planarity [37–39]:20
... elle ne saurait satisfaire les hommes en général; car, dans des cas assez ordinaires, elle ne s’accorde pas avec l’idée que tout homme, ayant ou non des connaissances spéciales de mathématiques, conçoit d’une manière plus ou moins vague et pourrait exprimer par les mots courbure d’une surface dans un point. ... Un géomètre peu soigneux pourrait donc dire, par exemple, que les surfaces cylindriques n’ont pas de courbure, tandis que tout le monde croit qu’elles sont courbes, comme on apprend à les considérer et à les nommer dès les premiers pas dans la vie et dans l’école. ... Voici donc de quelle manière je propose de mesurer la courbure d’une surface en un point, conformément à l’idée commune, dans les cas où il existe autour du point un fragment de la surface ayant partout un plan tangent.
A “good” curvature measure should only become zero for planes! Thus he defined the “Casorati curvature” as
This certainly works, but the way he explains the definition is hardly convincing. All that one may heartily agree on is
C caractérise par sa valeur zéro le manque total de courbure, de mème que la premiere des deux courbures des lignes, que l’on a déjà l’habitude de nommer tout simplement courbure. Avec cette signification du mot courbure on peut dire: Si la courbure est nulle en tout point, la surface est plane (la ligne est droite). Il n’y a que la surface plane (resp. la ligne droite) dont la courbure soit nulle en tout point.
Casorati’s notion did not receive universal acclaim. In a reaction in the same journal Eugène Catalan remarked that to say a sphere and a pseudo-sphere can have “the same curvature” is intuitively absurd [40]. This objection hangs on the very notion of “curvature,” so a short excursion on that topic seems in order.
Surface curvature cannot be completely represented on a linear scale. If one ignores spatial attitude, one ends up with two parameters. (Think of the two principal curvatures, or the Gaussian and mean curvature). Thus the Casorati curvature is in itself insufficient to characterize the nature of the relief (Figure 10).
However, Casorati correctly identifies a measure of “how much curvature.” This should be completed with a typification. Thus Catalan is right that the (unit) sphere and the pseudosphere appear different, but that does not prevent their curvature measure to be the same.
Unlike the principal curvatures, or the Gaussian and mean curvature, one might desire to characterize surface curvature by way of a quantity and a quality. The Casorati curvature is a natural measure of quantity. The quality might be the ratio of principal curvatures, say. Years ago I introduced a convenient “shape index” based on that notion [33,41]. It distinguishes the (unit) sphere from the pseudosphere, even though their “curvedness” is the same. The shape index is defined on an interval {−1, +1}, whose endpoints represent the umbilics (spheres). Shapes of opposite sign are related by a depth inversion, thus the pseudosphere resides at the origin [42].
In order to show how this works, I write a general quadric in terms of a linear combination of the sphere and the pseudosphere:
(Notice that (x2 − y2)/2 and xy are congruent, because (x2 − y2)/2 = uv, where
The principal curvatures are
Since {t, r, s} = {C sin S, C cos S cos2φ, C cos S sin2φ}, the parameters {C, S, 2φ} are special polar coordinates of “shape space.” The Casorati curvature is simply the distance from the origin. Fixing φ factors out orientation, fixing C then leaves us with a semicircle (notice that φ = φ + π) that parameterizes the quality (the shape index).
I continue with a different motivation of the Casorati curvature. In this case the root mean square deviation definition works very well. For using the weight
I merely preferred to change Casorati’s curvature into the “curvedness”
This is not essentially different from Casorati’s curvature, of course.
8. LEON BATTISTA ALBERTI’S ONTOLOGY AND ARTISTIC INTUITIONS
In order to get some feeling for the convex (or concave) and the saddle-like surfaces, here are some simple observations. The unit sphere (x2 + y2)/2 has indeed unit principal curvatures. An arbitrary line in the picture plane x0 + s cosφ, y0 + s sinφ can be seen as the projection of
Thus all curves on the sphere that project in straight lines are mutually congruent great circles. All have the same curvature, thus surface patches at different locations are perfectly congruent. Indeed, you can move the unit sphere in itself.
Repeating this for the unit “pseudosphere” (x2 − y2)/2 (Figure 11), yields
This shows that the curvature of curves that project on straight lines is cos2φ. Thus the principal curvatures are ±1, indeed concave and convex.
The lines in the direction φ = ±45° have zero curvature. Consider two of such lines that are parallel in the projection. These lines have different slopes, but they keep constant distance, like a railway track.22 Thus we find two mutually orthogonal families of parallel lines on the pseudosphere (Figure 11).
A Cartesian net of equally spaced lines in two mutually perpendicular directions can be bended into pseudospherical surfaces. Thus we have a Cartesian net on a curved surface! But, of course, any oblique line is curved.
However, to the “Euclidean Eye” such a deformation is not a bending because the “railway tracks” are no longer equidistant.
In mechanics and modern computer science the Casorati curvature (in Euclidean terms) has become known as the “bending energy.”23 This is related to continuum mechanics, the bending of plates. It immediately calls to mind the example of the bow. Might the experience with elastic deformations apply to higher dimensions (like surfaces)?
Nice as this would be, it is perhaps accidental. Too bad. The primordial curved surface is no doubt the outside of an egg shell. But it is not even possible to bend a flat sheet of paper into an egg shape. The situation is very unlike that in the case of the bow. Here Gauss’ discussion on intrinsic geometry becomes very relevant, as it was not at all for the bow.
In order to forge a flat sheet into some interesting surface the tailor uses cuts, seams and pleats, the cobbler and the brownsmith use extensive hammering to locally change the properties (the metric!) of the plate. Thus we lack the kind of experience we may have in the case of the curvature of beams.
In Euclidean space only spheres and planes can be arbitrarily moved in themselves. If you rub two solids together long enough, using some type of abrasive, they will automatically assume a spherical form, one convex, one concave. This is the time honored way to grind optical lenses. Aspherical surfaces were very hard to produce before the advent of computer controlled grinding machines.24 In order to produce a flat surface one works pairwise on three pieces.
For larger flats, say billiard tables, one has to proceed differently. Frequent testing with straight templates applied at different locations and in different directions is necessary.
The final “flatness” of such surfaces is defined statistically, much as we did in the curvature definition “against the grain.” Such tests and measures are an important part of various technologies. The corresponding literature is completely unrelated to the mathematical literature on curvature.
In the case of surfaces most of our understanding comes from haptic and visual experiences with found objects. Think of eggs, fruits, leaves, stones, landforms and so forth. Alberti was an intellectual who really thought about the topic, but – apart from the degenerate cases with one or two vanishing curvatures – could only come up with concavities and convexities. He completely missed the saddle shapes. Yet saddle shapes are by no means rare. On a Gaussian random surface the saddle-like points are actually in the majority [28]!
Indeed, we have found that even modern Western intellectuals are largely “saddle–blind.” Why might that be?
If you dig for sculptor’s intuitions (they ought to be experts!) you find that the academies tell you to “go for the convexities, the concavities (they probably include the saddles) will take care of themselves!” [44].
Given that the human or animal unclad body [45] has been a major topic for the sculptor since the earliest times (Figure 12), this actually starts to make sense.
The articulation of body surface (I’m not talking about extremities as related to the trunk) is due to the musculature, which is slightly softened by layers of fat and elastic skin. The muscles attach to bones and have their swelling bellies away from the point of attachment. Thus the body surface is governed by dimples (the places where muscles attach to bony crests just below the skin), ruts (the grooves between muscle bodies) and ovoid shapes (the bellies of the muscles).
The result is that the body relief is similar to a bunch of grapes. Benvenuto Cellini (1500–1571)25 likened the treatment by Bandinelli – in an obviously pejorative manner – as similar to a sack of melons put in some corner [47]. I feel he had a point (see Figure 13).26
9. MORE TO FOLLOW UP
Another reason for the more than coincidental dominance of convexity is that objects of limited size tend to be convex. One sees this in beach pebbles, where the shapes are due to random abrasion [48].
In organic bodies one has the additional factor that it is good to maximize volume for a given area, as it counteracts drying out. This is obvious in many fruits. Indeed this type of optimality pops up in many physically/physiologically distinct settings (e.g. [49]).
These factors are in no way exhaustive. There are numerous processes that play a role and the biologically relevant costs are diverse too. We tend to be sensitive to this and look with some pleasure on shapes that reflect some kind of intuitive optimum.
So much for a view on
CONFLICTS OF INTEREST
The author declares they have no conflicts of interest.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The work was supported by the DFG Collaborative Research Center SFB TRR 135 headed by Karl Gegenfurtner (Justus-Liebig Universität Giessen, Germany) and by the program by the Flemish Government (METH/14/02), awarded to Johan Wagemans. Jan Koenderink is supported by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation. The author is grateful to Andrea van Doorn for many discussions and corrections.
Footnotes
Yes, another Dutchman, like me. I’m proud of him, you will have your own preference, no doubt.
For many “archaic” references I do not specify complete data in the bibliography. In all cases you should use the Internet. You will find facsimile, reprints, OCR searchable texts and translations into various languages, mostly downloadable for free. As a retired professor with very limited means I read mainly the latter.
I refer to a tubular, segmented worm of the phylum Annelida. They are remarkably flexible, although I’ve never seen one that knotted itself.
Language proper started maybe 200,000 years ago, but proto-languages date perhaps 2 million years back.
Thus we understand an alarm clock, but are forever unable to understand a rabbit or a potato.
A Pine-wood (Pinus sylvestris) fragment from Mannheim-Vogelstang (Germany) of early Magdalenian age is likely to have been a bow. It wouldn’t have been longer than around 110 cm. I don’t think it was a fire bow (similar to a drill), because a little too large for that. The power of a bow as smallish as this would amply suffice to kill rabbits, although simply trapping them might be more productive.
With exception of Australasia and Oceania.
The invention of the bow is perhaps even more important than that of the wheel. Perhaps coincidentally, both are closely related to curvature. The wheel dates from the late Neolithic, the advent of the Bronze Age. The potter’s wheel goes back to perhaps 4500–3300
Elasticity, Young’s modulus.
Second moment of area, or “moment of inertia”.
To be converted to the kinetic energy of the arrow at the moment of “loosing.”
The bending stiffness.
If you want to try, the painting is the centre panel of a triptych at the Catharijneconvent at Utrecht, where I live.
Either the anterior nodal point of the eye, or the center of rotation of the eye-ball, given the viewing distance it makes no difference.
Also called “nil-square infinitesimals.”
An example of a circle as a curve of constant radius would be u2 = 1, which consists of the two lines ±1 + ε v (v ∈ (−∞, +∞)). It is the geometrical locus of all points at a fixed distance from a given point.
Remember that the Euclidean computation of the curvature implies
“Infinitesimals” have been a major headache for ages. As a physics student I was drilled in the (then) correct mathematics. Of course, we secretly used the nil-square infinitesimals all the time, although we didn’t know it. Especially Leibniz’s triangle F(x + εy) = F(x) + εydF(x)/dx proved very convenient. We felt guilty in interpreting “≈” as “=,” although F(x + εy) = F(x) + εydF(x)/dx represents the full Taylor series! Nowadays curricula are being adjusted.
My driver’s seat is concave–concave rather than convex–concave because I point my legs forward instead of to the sides.
I read the Italian references years ago in a library, but unfortunately I have no copies. As a retired professor I have no facilities to acquire them now. I downloaded the French paper from the Utrecht University library.
Of course, I understand Casorati’s hesitation to draw the square root, after all, he was a mathematician.
Such lines would appear “skew” to the Euclidean Eye. This is one definition of parallelity. Another one that is sometimes useful implies the same line in projection, same slopes, but different depths.
For a quadric 1/2(a20x2 + 2a11xy + a02y2) (typically the leading part of a Taylor series, whose zeroth and first orders are ignored because accounted for) one defines the “bending energy” as
Thus grinding parabolic mirrors for telescopes involved much trial and error.
Cellini’s biography reads like a fantastic rogue story. Moreover, you’ll pick up lots of interesting workshop practice and samples of Late Renaissance taste. There are numerous reprints and translations. I particularly like Goethe’s German one. The vita was started in 1558 (age of 58). It suddenly stops in 1563 as Cellini departs toward Pisa.
The passage reads: Well, then, this virtuous school [of Florence] says... that nothing worse was ever seen; his sprawling shoulders are like the two pommels of an ass’ pack-saddle; his breasts and all the muscles of the body are not portrayed from a man, but from a big sack full of melons set upright against a wall. The loins seem to be modelled from a bag of lanky pumpkins;...
REFERENCES
Cite this article
TY - JOUR AU - Jan Koenderink PY - 2020 DA - 2020/02/23 TI - Curvature Against the Grain JO - Growth and Form SP - 9 EP - 19 VL - 1 IS - 1 SN - 2589-8426 UR - https://doi.org/10.2991/gaf.k.200124.004 DO - 10.2991/gaf.k.200124.004 ID - Koenderink2020 ER -